So what’s
behind this big transition? “Symbolic stuff kicked
in 50,000 years ago, and that led to all manner of thoroughly modern
behaviors.” That’s the usual explanation for the Modern Transition,
and it’s not a bad one.
You may have noticed, however, that I have avoided talking about
symbols. That’s because I consider symbols an inadequate summary,
not because I think the explanation “wrong.” Here’s the OED on
symbol:
2.
Something that stands for, represents, or denotes something else (not by
exact resemblance, but by vague suggestion, or by some accidental or
conventional relation); esp. a material object representing or taken to
represent something immaterial or abstract, as a being, idea, quality, or
condition; a representative or typical figure, sign, or token.
But at root, it’s an
association between dissimilar things, much like Pavlov’s dog salivating
for the bell in addition to dinner itself. The important aspect for
language purposes appears when the symbol stands in for something
compounded of many other things, especially at a higher level of
organization (more later) than mere objects and simple actions – say, the
notion of a Rain God or an ecosystem.
If one word has to suffice to summarize a broad collection of new
abilities – perhaps a bad idea to start with – I’d certainly pick a
different word than the one popular throughout the twentieth
century. With notable exceptions (do read Terry Deacon’s
The Symbolic Species), when people latch
on to the idea of symbolic stuff, they stop thinking about the parts and
pieces – and how they are coherently assembled at different levels of
organization. People go away thinking that they’ve achieved
something by labeling all of it “symbolic” and may just argue in a
circle. Looking at the same material through the eyes of process,
how neural circuits turn one thing into another, is more satisfying – and
it enables you to spot more candidates for the big step
up.
That there is a stand-in is not what needs emphasis. Human minds are
indeed more capable of both broad categories and fine distinctions but
what’s important here is that the referent is a complicated compound,
often framed or structured. Yet what I am calling “structured stuff”
goes well beyond framing. Structuring really makes long sentences
fly, and likely complicated thoughts as well.
What else comes before
structured language? So far
I’ve discussed some things that might be called protostructure:
staging intermediate products in food preparation and toolmaking, framing,
and theory of mind. I’ve mentioned imitation as an amplifier.
I mentioned protolanguage earlier, but let me now spell out what Derek
Bickerton means by it.
This unstructured language is what you see in toddlers, speakers of
pidgins (the shared vocabulary between people who lack a common language,
spoken without grammar), and in some stroke patients with aphasia.
It is often heavily augmented with gestures. Most of all, the
sentences are short in the manner of what two-year-olds produce – you can
guess the meaning without any help from word order or inflections. This is
the level of production that can be achieved in tutored bonobos like Kanzi
and Panbinisha (they can do somewhat better at understanding than with
production, much as I do with my rusty agrammatical German). A lot
can be inferred from context.
Long
sentences, however, are simply too ambiguous without some mutually
understood conventions about internal structuring into phrases and
clauses. A clause (it contains a verb) may be embedded in a phrase
and vice versa. The structuring conventions that help you figure out
“who did what to whom” are called syntax and each dialect has a different
way of doing things. There are five other permutations of the
subject-verb-object word order used in English declarative sentences, and
all can be found in some language around the world. Many languages
convey structure with the aid of word endings that mark the role that the
word is meant to play in that particular sentence; for example,
–ly is an English ending
that usually means that the word is going to modify a
verb.
“Universal grammar” is simply the tendency of all human groups to draw
from a restricted set of structuring possibilities; not every structuring
scheme appears to be possible, and that restriction likely says something
about the limitations of the human brain. For example, you can move
one word out of place – say, in making “What did she give to him?” out of the
standard order “She gave what to him?” – but two things cannot be moved in the same
sentence without making it hopelessly ambiguous.
The
human faculty of language appears to be organized like the
genetic code – hierarchical, generative, recursive, and
virtually limitless with respect to its scope of expression….
Most current commentators agree that, although bees dance,
birds sing, and chimpanzees grunt, these systems of
communication differ qualitatively from human language.
In particular, animal communication systems lack the rich
expressive and open-ended power of human language (based on
humans’ capacity for recursion).
– Marc
Hauser, Noam Chomsky, Tecumseh Fitch,
2002
Syntax is the best-studied case of
structured thought, one of the candidates for what “paid for” the rest,
and certainly the earliest one to appear in modern childhood (kids pick
one up between 18 and 36 months). Once you have a syntax, you can
convey complicated thoughts. And the acquisition of syntax likely
tunes up the brain to do other structured tasks.
The step up to syntax is indeed a big one, as it involves such things as
recursion. In saying “I think I saw him leave to go home,” you are
nesting four sentences like the Russian babushka dolls.
Structuring helps you discover the meaning of the sentence (the mental
model in the speaker’s mind) but it isn’t the meaning itself.
Chomsky’s famous sentence to show the independence of syntax from
semantics, “Colorless green ideas sleep furiously,” may not make any
sense, but it doesn’t ring any structural alarm bells in our minds in the
manner of “Colorless ideas furiously sleep green.”
Syntax is not necessarily a tree, though people who like maps are quite
attracted to the technique of diagramming a sentence using branch points
with only two daughter branches. At the heart of the structured
sentence are clauses (easy to spot because each has a verb) and
phrases. It turns out that they can nest inside one another.
“John gave a present to Mary in the park last night” has only one verb but
you can augment it by substituting “the present his sister bought” clause
for “a present.”
If you’re not a map person, you might like argument structure
better. This complementary way of looking at structure emphasizes
the sentence as a little drama in which words play roles. A noun
might be the actor or the recipient – you have to figure it out from
clues. Some words, especially verbs, prompt you to find other words
that go with them. But not just any word. It has to be a word that
can play the particular role.
In any of its equivalents in the world’s languages, “give” is a verb with
three roles to fill (there can also be associated nouns filling optional
roles such as time and place, but give needs three nouns to fill its
mandatory roles). You need to find a noun that can play the role of
the giver (“John”). Another noun for the thing given (“a
present”). And a third noun that can play the recipient. Because an
inanimate object (“present”) cannot be an actor, you can immediately
eliminate one role possibility.
Try to speak a sentence without one of the three essential nouns and your
listener will be perplexed and go in search of the missing word. A
missing subject probably means “you” as in the imperative form, “Give me
that.” But a billboard with a fragmentary sentence “Give him…” will
cause a double take (exactly what the ad agency was trying to achieve)
while you search for the pictorial equivalent of the object to be
given.
The so-called intransitive verbs such as sleep may not require much
in the way of a supporting cast (“He slept.”), but you can always add
optional phrases (“on the sofa” or “during the lecture”) or adverbs such
as quietly or poorly. Some languages such as
Latin rely heavily on such “inflections”; word order may not matter very
much. In English, many inflections have disappeared in recent
centuries; word order is often your main clue about what roles to assign,
as in the subject-verb-object order of a simple declarative
sentence. But word order is only one clue to structure, not the main
thing.
The basic idea of argument structure, and of the lexicon in Chomsky’s more
recent minimalist grammar, is that each word has some possible roles that
form part of its mental baggage. You simply know them from
experience. You can’t “break the blanket” because a blanket doesn’t
have the right attributes to be breakable. You can tear it or burn
it or ruin it, but not break it.
Presented with a sentence to analyze, you try to fit the pieces together
in a way that makes sense. Every required role must be filled, and
no words should be left over once you have guessed the optional roles –
your mental model of the sentence now hangs together. With the
meaning thus extracted, you move on to the next sentence and its
coherence-finding game. If a sentence is incoherent, we ask for a
repeat or just accept a reasonable candidate and move on. If the
sentence seems to have two perfectly reasonable alternative
interpretations that leave us undecided, it may be humorous enough to make
us laugh.
The verb is usually the starting point of an analysis as it tells you how
many obligatory roles must be satisfied by the other words of the
sentence. Some like “sleep” have only one role to fill, others such
as “bring” and “give” have three; “bet” takes four as you also have to
specify the condition of the bet. So understanding a sentence with
syntax is like solving a jigsaw puzzle.
Language
is all about taking a mental model of relationships in your mind – say,
“who did what to whom” – and, via gestures or speech, getting someone else
to guess exactly what you are thinking. Language can get across a
model of relationships even to someone who doesn’t share the context, even
models of relationships that haven’t happened yet, even about abstract
concepts like washing machines that eat socks.
Language only needs to be good enough. We often don’t need to finish
sentences, because the rest can be guessed so easily. We just need
enough hints to allow us to guess correctly most of the time. The task of language is to convey such
relationships in an open-ended way, being able to convey novel
amalgamations and have the listener effortlessly get the right idea.
If you are sticking to simple relationships, unstructured protolanguage
may suffice. But if you want to speak a long sentence, the ambiguity
is a killer unless you can spot all of those prompts for frames and roles
that we call grammar and syntax.
Syntax is our best-studied case of structured thought, given how many ways
there are to do the structuring job and how many schemes seem impossible,
not used in any human language. But syntax is not the only type of
structured thought, and perhaps not even the first one to
evolve.
Other structured aspects
of thought are multistage planning,
games with rules that constrain possible moves, chains of logic,
structured music – and a fascination with discovering hidden order, with
imagining how things hang together. This structured suite likely
enabled the giant step up to the modern mind of Homo
sapiens sapiens.
Let me unpack what I mean by all the structured
stuff.
Planning is not what a
squirrel does as winter approaches. Earlier I made that distinction
in the context of physiological mechanisms. Now note that from the
evolutionary perspective, there is nothing novel about winter coming, even
for a young squirrel. It has happened every year to every squirrel
for as long as there have been squirrels in the temperate zone, and said
squirrel comes from an unbroken line of squirrels that survived winter’s
dormancy of food resources. Like mating, nest building, and
nurturing behaviors, food hoarding is too important to be left to learning
or innovation. Planning pertains to novel situations, not learning
or instinct.
Note that instincts are
another nice example of framing: when a naïve animal is placed in an
important setting for the first time, out pops an intricate
never-experienced-before behavior like mating or nurturing.
“Context, context, context” is what those real-estate agents really mean
by their mantra about the three most important considerations, “location,
location, location.”
Behaviorally modern
humans plan for things that have never happened before, and in terms of
choices. ("Well, obviously if we go to the country this weekend, we
can’t go to the baseball game Saturday night.") Foresight often
involves contingencies, another type of structure. ("We can go to
the country this weekend unless I have to work Saturday, in which case
maybe we can go to a movie on Sunday.") And by the time children
reach school age, we start holding them responsible for having some
foresight, and in a way that we do not apply to younger children or
pets. (In the immortal words of my mother, "Well, you should have
thought about that before you did it!")
It is useful to imagine a
version of structured thought that is too slow for repartee. It
might be handy when you have time to think about things overnight, and so
it can influence agendas and contingent planning – but even if you could
speak a novel sentence aloud, no one might be able to interpret it without
thinking about it overnight. We usually assume spoken syntax comes
first in evolution as it does in childhood, but overnight contemplation
for planning could have been an early payoff for structured thought,
even before language.
Chains of
logic, like
those multistage novel plans, are considerably more difficult to handle
than the simple forms of logic seen in other animals.
Logical trains of inference allow us to connect remote causes through
intermediate stages to present effects. The basic element may be the
primitive two-stage “after this therefore because of this” attribution,
but reasoning in long chains is something at which we excel.
A supposed chain is, in reality, often a web instead, but the
notion of being impelled down a path is very strong in us and it’s much
more difficult for us to think about multiple causation. Most of the
things that happen in the world have multiple causes, of course, so we
make a lot of errors of attribution.
When not all the elements
are clear, we have a propensity to guess at chains of causation.
This is very useful in doing science. You can, of course, fool
yourself very easily, which is why it is so important to keep track of
what is provisional or pretense and what is well
established.
Games have made-up rules
that you have to consult before making your move. Hopscotch and
dance may have elements of play but they are also flexibly structured in
ways that constrain choices. But what I have in mind here
is something with an arbitrary framework of allowed moves, against which
possible moves must be checked before acting.
Indeed, once four-year-olds have the ability to say “who did what to
whom,” they love to keep track of the actions of others (and report
deviations to the person in charge). It becomes a game.
Narrative is closely related to
framework-checking because we develop some standards for a good story –
and not just epics but the everyday multifaceted stories, such as what we
did for lunch. There’s almost a “script” (with whom, where, what
eaten, what discussed, and so forth). If some part is missing, we
often inquire. So narrative is pattern
on an even longer time scale than a sentence and it often has some blanks
to fill in, just as in those “give him” sentences.
I suspect that logical
chains grow out of small-scale storytelling. Someone pouring coffee
into a cup provides a small story with familiar parts (called image
schemas), the coffee pouring from one container, flowing
along a path and then being contained by a second
object.
As
Mark Turner points out in The Literary Mind, partitioning the world
into object categories also involves partitioning the world into small
stories: catching a ball, throwing it, sitting on a chair, drinking the
coffee. Many animals can do some of this, but modern humans can
weave small stories into considerable narratives. We use such chains
to evaluate the wisdom of possible actions, to plan better ones, and when
it all hangs together well enough to connect the underpinnings, we say
that we have “understood” or “explained” things.
Music can be simply
patterned as in rhythm and melody, and it can additionally be structured
as in harmony. Multivoiced music is what
you get into with singing a fifth or an octave above someone else.
It is particularly impressive when one person can manage both, as when
the left hand plays a different melody from the right
hand.
In
western music, this is not much more than a thousand years old. The
counter melodies of the baroque, which Bach elaborated from church music
that had already proved its emotional appeal in plainchant, are only a few
centuries old. The philosopher Karl Popper said that the development
of multivoiced music was “possibly the most unprecedented, original,
indeed miraculous achievement of our Western civilization, not excluding
science.”
Rhythm itself may be much older and the solo voice might be an outgrowth
of ancient storytelling techniques, the melody (and alliteration and
rhyme) used as an aid to memory about what comes next. Music may
elaborate social cohesion (marching music as a technique of the
warmonger). But there may also be individual advantages to be gained
from showing off unusual abilities, not only musical abilities but
virtuoso performances of other sorts (intricate dances, bower building,
blindman’s buff). When females choose males (rather than males
excluding one another from access to females), genetic fitness tends to be
judged by just such complex behavioral proxies.
Discovering
hidden patterns is seen in music, jigsaw puzzles, and doing
science. We take great pleasure in “getting it.”
We love
to see patterns emerging from seeming chaos, whether in doing a crossword
puzzle or in doing science. Coherence-finding is probably part of
the source of our musical pleasure in listening to the left hand’s rhythm
interacting with the right hand’s melody.
As
with those fill-in-the-blank test sentences, we’re always guessing about
missing parts, trying to make wholes out of fragments.
Beyond-the-apes intelligence seems to be about making a guess that
discovers some new underlying order – finding the solution to a problem or
the logic in an argument, happening upon an appropriate analogy, creating
a pleasing harmony or a witty reply, correctly predicting what’s likely to
happen next.
Indeed, you routinely guess what comes next, even subconsciously.
That’s why a joke’s punch line or a P.D.Q. Bach musical parody brings you
up short – you were subconsciously predicting and were surprised by the
unanticipated ending.
Note that music
beyond rhythm, planning beyond the predictable seasons, and the logical
chaining of ideas are all things that involve the novel, not just learned
repetitions like singing the national anthem. Novel structured
stuff, with its search for coherence, is what we usually call “higher
intellectual function.”
The structuring that I have in mind for higher intellectual functions is
not just a simple chain of events or intermediate products. It is
more like a symphony – and that reminds me of another important symphony
that the brain had been producing for a million years before
intellect.
I call them a
“structured suite” because I suspect
that they share a lot of the same neural machinery in the brain,
one of
the reasons why some functions might come (and go, in strokes or senility)
as a package deal. Perhaps the mental
machinery for structuring is shared in part with some nonintellectual
functions as well.
Accurate throwing (not just flinging,
which many chimps do, but practicing to hit smaller and smaller targets)
is not usually a set piece like a dart throw or basketball free throw
where the idea is to perform the action exactly the same way as your
hard-earned standard. Throwing at a prospect for dinner usually
involves something novel: the target is not at the same distance or the
same elevation as one of your standards; perhaps it is moving, too.
And throwing, much more than such ballistic motions as spitting, involves
a structured plan. Indeed, planning a throw has some nested stages,
strongly reminiscent of syntax.
The highest velocity action is in the wrist movement, but planning it
requires you to take account of what the elbow is doing: wrist
flicks, where mistakes matter most, are nested inside elbow
uncocking. What you want to achieve is a certain launch velocity,
but you want the launch to occur at just the correct angle to the
vertical. That’s not a matter for the wrist alone. You need to
take into account what the elbow is doing – or rather, since this is
advance planning, what the elbow plan is. You have to estimate –
guess, in other words – its motion.
Elbow planning needs to know what the shoulder is doing. And the
shoulder too has a forward velocity due to what the whole trunk is doing,
that forward velocity added by the legs. So planning a throw is a
nested problem, just like understanding “I think I saw him leave to go
home.”
You don’t do this as some assembly line during “get set,” marching from
the fingers back up to shoulders, but you do have to juggle the finger,
wrist, elbow, shoulder, and body plans, coordinating until you get the
overall symphony right (as judged by your memories of
similar-but-not-identical situations). While there are a number of
combinations that might suffice for a given target location, they have to
hang together in just the right way or you’ll miss the target and go
hungry. You need, in other words, a coherent plan: all of the parts
(and there are about a hundred muscles involved) have to form an
internally compatible plan. So, if the target is not standing at the
location of one of your well-rehearsed set pieces, you need make a novel,
staged, coherent plan. And then execute it in an eighth of a second,
getting all those muscles to come in at just the right time and with just
the right strength.
It was probably an expensive bit of Darwinian engineering, to get throws
to be as good as what even eight-year-olds can accomplish on the
playground of my neighborhood school. Fortunately, once paid for by
its usefulness in feeding the family with ever more frequent helpings of
high calorie, nontoxic food, the neural machinery can perform other kinds
of planning tasks as well, even for free.
Even without something
for “free,” this sounds like
heresy. That’s because arguments about useful adaptations seem to
assume (even when there is no need) that one cortical area is dedicated to
one function. As I mentioned earlier, you’d almost think that better
throwing abilities ought to raise a bump on the head that could be labeled
Hand-Arm Planning Center.
It would be separate, of course (another beginners’ error), from
another bump labeled the Language Module. There are two quick
arguments that nicely serve to illuminate this understandable beginners’
mistake.
One is that there may not be sufficient genetic variety to expand just one
little region of the brain; the only variety available may be to increase
major portions of the brain together – and that’s what most of the
evolutionary data suggests. “Increase one area, increase them all”
may be the general rule. There are important exceptions: some
lineages can increase the olfactory areas of the brain without also
increasing the cerebral cortex. In general, raising a specialized
bump is not an available option, however efficient it might seem as a
first guess. (As I’ll mention later, our intuitive notions of
biological engineering often do not correspond to Darwinian reality, not
any better than our intuitive physics matches up with Newtonian reality –
and certainly not Einstein’s.)
Second, though some of the best-understood regions of the brain such as
primary visual cortex seem rather dedicated to a specialty, much of
association cortex seems multifunctional. Certainly there is much
evidence suggesting that oral-facial movement planning can overlap with
that for hand-arm – and with that for language, both sensory and motor
aspects. So we might even see “improve one function, improve some
others in passing.”
Whatever economist
said that “There is no such thing as
a free lunch” obviously didn’t absorb the lessons from Darwin and his
successors. Pay via natural selection for one functionality like
planning or language, and you may get the others such as music mostly “for
free.”
Let us assume that, however we got them, we have some brain circuits that
are capable of running a process for making multistage coherent plans, and
judging them for quality against your memory of what’s reasonable and
safe. Can you use them for other movement sequences as well
as hand-arm?
Not only is there is a great deal of multiple use in evolution but you can
see a nice concrete reminder on many a street corner – some missing
concrete. Wheelchair considerations paid for curb
cuts but soon 99 percent of their use was for things
that would never have paid their way – baby carriages, grocery carts,
skateboards, wheeled suitcases, bicycles, and so on. Maybe one of
those secondary uses will eventually pay for further improvements but
pay-before-using is not required.
When did spare-time uses develop for the neural machinery for planning
throws? Hammering was likely the earliest, though I wouldn’t push
cause-and-effect too far here. With shared machinery, you can have
coevolution with synergies: better throwing might improve, in
passing, the ability to hammer accurately. And vice versa.
Though I am fond of accurate throwing as an early prime mover, remember
that any of the uses of structured thought might improve the others,
different ones at various times. Even before the transition,
language probably started paying its way.
One of the free uses of the curb cut has already paid for a subsequent
improvement. I can remember when traffic jams occurred at the
wheelchair ramps at airports. The wheeled suitcases would queue up,
awaiting their chance at the slot, and so in the newer airports, curb cuts
were made as wide as the crosswalk. When robotic developments enable
both wheelchairs and suitcases to climb stairs, they’ll find curbs
easy. Indeed, the curb cuts may become obsolete for their original
functions, though still frequented by bicycles and skateboards. By
the time that their original functions are forgotten, skateboarding will
probably have evolved into a religion. The skateboarders will surely
claim the curb cuts as their ancestral sites of worship
– and try to exclude pedestrians.
In seeing the curb cut as created for its then-current best use, the
skateboarders will be making the same inference that we make now when we
posit that the evolution of the big brain is all about intelligence.
Maybe. Maybe not.
Secondary use initially gets a free ride, and it doesn’t necessarily
retire the original use in the manner of Darwin’s example, the fish’s swim
bladder that turns, after an intermediate period of dual use, into a
lung. (That’s where Darwin also cautions about going overboard on
adaptations via natural selection, observing that conversions of function
can also be quite important.)
The structure can remain multifunctional. The name often changes to
reflect the most obvious high-order use - and since the brain is very good about multiple
use, maybe our high-order uses ought to be seen in this curb-cut
context. All of this, of course, is meant as parable: I want
you to see the evolutionary development of complex thought as a parallel
to the recent expansion of curb-cut uses.
But just because some secondary use is possible doesn’t mean it instantly
happens. We were likely capable of structured music (what you’re
doing when the left hand plays a different tune from the right hand) just
after the big transition, long before Western music got around to using it
about a thousand years ago. Just because novel symphonies of
hand-arm movement commands had been getting better and better for a
million years doesn’t mean that secondary use for spoken language had to
happen, or say when.
So when do
kids pick up structured stuff from
their experiences in life? Modern children can do it from speech
between 18 and 36 months of age, even before they can tie their shoes
(fine movement control matures more slowly) – provided, of course, that
their culture provides them with lots of examples of structured stuff to
puzzle over.
Let us say that, back 150,000 years ago, it was only when practicing
accurate throwing at age eight that a lot of novel structured stuff was
experienced. Protolanguage was perhaps around, but short sentences
can be understood without looking for structural hints as to roles.
All of that practice throwing at novel targets served, let us say, to
softwire the brain in the manner of learning, so that adult performance
was better on structured stuff.
But picking up structured stuff also depends on an individual’s
acquisitiveness, as in those modern kids picking up many new words a
day. Some kids are acquisitive of structured stuff earlier than
others; it’s probably some bell-shaped curve. And their performance
as adults on structured stuff depends strongly (if we are to judge from
the deaf kids without sign language environments) on a window of
opportunity (to be dramatic, let us say it opens at age two and flattens
at five years of age, that thick line).
So being precocious pays off as an adult, because you do a better job of
softwiring for structured stuff, having done it earlier than the average
child. There are three cases to consider:
·
The age when interested
doesn’t really overlap with the window of above-average softwiring
opportunity. So the more precocious kids (left side of the top bell
curve) aren’t better as adults than the average kids, no matter when
culture exposes them to structured stuff.
·
The precocious kids are
overlapping with the sensitive period for softwiring the brain for
structured stuff – that earlier-is-better segment of the thick line – but
culture doesn’t provide any structured examples that early, so they never
tune up when earlier is better. (The tragedy of the modern deaf kids
with hearing parents, but also what anatomically moderns might have been
like before syntax.)
·
Culture provides early
examples of structured stuff via, say, speech. Now earlier is better
for eventual adult performance. And those successful adults are
providing the next round of variations centered on their (skewed) average
via Darwin’s inheritance principle. So the more precocious of the
offspring of the previously precocious are even better as adults.
With this, successive generations can keep marching to the left, back up
the earlier-is-better part of the thick line.
This is just another
aspect of what are called epigenetic factors in development, where the
environment serves to trigger an alternative path in development. In
the case of plants, it is sunlight that provides a cue to a new branch as
to whether to grow upward and sprout leaves or to grow downward and
develop root hairs. Culture too can provide important cues for making
development choices and directional selection can move the succeeding
generations up the curve. Evolution interacts with development via
the environment (the research area is known as EvoDevo) and that’s why
nature-nurture and genes-culture are such false
dichotomies.
For now, note that none of this requires very much of what is usually
posited by the archaeologists: some new genes to initiate the
transition. Even the tweaks in acquisitiveness might come later, if
the curves originally overlapped the window of better softwiring
opportunity. In just one generation of kids finally being exposed to
structured stuff at earlier ages, the next generation of adults would be
far more capable, thanks to softwiring in youth. (In fact, it need
not wait until the next generation: older children are usually the
frequent companions of younger children, and so a mother speaking
structured sentences can infect her children, who themselves infect other
children a few years later.)
So the simplest
version of a rapid ascent to structured thought looks like this:
·
PRE: Structured stuff is
learned in later childhood with accurate throwing and
toolmaking.
·
TRANSITION: Some older
children and adults manage to slowly add structure to protolanguage
utterances.
·
POST: Young children are now exposed to structured
stuff via the speech of caregivers, even before they can “tie their
shoes,” and they then softwire their brains to really fly as adults.
But because structured stuff via one route may carry over to such things
as planning and logic, most of the structured suite pops into place in a
few generations.
So
the archaeologist’s summary of what “behaviorally
modern” involves – abstract thought, planning in depth, innovation,
symbols, storytelling – overlaps with higher intellectual function.
But a “symbolic” formulation doesn’t hint at the underlying unity that
I’ve been covering here.
My point is that much of this behavioral modernity is structured – syntax,
contingent plans, music, logical chains, narratives, games with rules,
house-of-cards analogies – and that we compulsively guess to fill in
missing pieces in the inferred structure. Guessing at structured
stuff means we can make a lot of mistakes, so we have to be constantly
concerned with quality.
Quality and coherence are also what limits creativity. I will devote
an entire chapter to creativity after saying something about how much of
higher intellectual function seems half-baked, what you ordinarily see in
a prototype rather than a finished, well-engineered product.
Perfection you don’t get, not from Darwinian evolution. And the
quality controls are spotty. But culture – especially education and
medicine – can sometimes patch things up, if society works hard enough at
it.